Monday 31 July 2017

Toomas Karmo: Part J: Perception, Action, and "Subjectivity"

Quality assessment:



On the 5-point scale current in Estonia, and surely in nearby nations, and familiar to observers of the academic arrangements of the late, unlamented, Union of Soviet Socialist Republics (applying the easy and lax standards Kmo deploys in his grubby imaginary "Aleksandr Stepanovitsh Popovi nimeline sangarliku raadio instituut" (the "Alexandr Stepanovitch Popov Institute of Heroic Radio") and his  grubby imaginary "Nikolai Ivanovitsh Lobatshevski nimeline sotsalitsliku matemaatika instituut" (the "Nicolai Ivanovich Lobachevsky Institute of Socialist Mathematics") - where, on the lax and easy grading philosophy of the twin Institutes, 1/5 is "epic fail", 2/5 is "failure not so disastrous as to be epic", 3/5 is "mediocre pass", 4/5 is "good", and 5/5 is "excellent"): 4/5. Justification: There was enough time to write out the  necessary points to reasonable length.


Revision history:


All times in these blog "revision histories" are stated in UTC (Universal Coordinated Time/ Temps Universel Coordoné,  a precisification of the old GMT, or "Greenwich Mean Time"), in the ISO-prescribed YYYYMMDDThhmmZ timestamping format. UTC currently leads Toronto civil time by 4 hours and currently lags Tallinn civil time by 3 hours.

  • 20170801T1623Z/version 3.1.0: Kmo added two amplificatory paragraphs, starting with the words "It will help some readers if I add that my remark about X possibly-occurring-without-a-cause has a parallel in". He reserved the right to upload minor, nonsubstantive, purely cosmetic, revisions over the coming 48 hours, as here-undocumented versions 3.1.1, 3.1.2, 3.1.3, ... . 
  • 20170801T2347Z/version 3.0.0: Kmo finished converting his finegrained outline into full-sentences prose. He now embarked on a minor process of checking and polishing. He reserved the right to upload minor, nonsubstantive, purely cosmetic, revisions over the coming 48 hours, as here-undocumented versions 3.0.1, 3.0.2, 3.0.3, ... . 
  • 20170801T2041Z/version 2.0.0: Kmo finished converted his coarsegrained outline into a duly polished finegrained outline. He hoped in the coming 3 hours to finish converting this, in turn, into full-sentences prose.
  • 20170801T1728Z/version 1.0.0: Kmo, now doing better in his difficulties, managed to upload a duly polished coarsegrained outline. He hoped to convert this over the coming 3 hours into a duly polished finegrained outline, and then still later on 2017-08-01 to convert the finegrained outline into full-sentences prose.
  • 20170801T0256Z: Sorry, ill with depression. Will try to get the material up in next couple of days.



[CAUTION: A bug in the blogger server-side software has in some past months shown a propensity to insert inappropriate whitespace at some points in some of my posted essays. If a screen seems to end in empty space, keep scrolling down. The end of the posting is not reached until the usual blogger "Posted by Toomas (Tom) Karmo at" appears. - The blogger software has also shown a propensity, at any rate when coupled with my erstwhile, out-of-date, Web-authoring uploading browser, to generate HTML that gets formatted in different ways on different downloading browsers. Some downloading browsers have sometimes perhaps not correctly read in the entirety of the "Cascading Style Sheets"  (CSS) which on all ordinary Web servers control the browser placement of margins, sidebars, and the like. If you suspect CSS problems in your particular browser, be patient: it is probable that while some content has been shoved into some odd place (for instance, down to the bottom of your browser, where it ought to appear in the right-hand margin), all the server content has been pushed down into your browser in some place or other. - Finally, there may be blogger vagaries, outside my control, in font sizing or interlinear spacing or right-margin justification. - Anyone inclined to help with trouble-shooting, or to offer other kinds of technical advice, is welcome to write me via Toomas.Karmo@gmail.com.]



It is necessary to begin by recapitulating, and expanding, the Kaila-Strawson "sound universe" scenario with which my last installment ended. 

Imagine it this week, Gentle Reader, in terms of a sudden, radical, change in what you are undergoing. In the minutes leading up to 4:00 pm today, you have been "greening", and have been seeing a chain of ordinary physical things, among them a sunlit lawn, in greening. In your right hand has been a glass with some ice-chilled drink. This glass, at a temperature only a little above 0oC, is one of a chain of ordinary physical things - among them are also events in your nerves, starting with nerves in some correspondingly cold finger flesh, and continuing with neurons within the right arm, the spinal cord, and ultimately the skull - which you have been feeling in "being-chilled". Now, at 4:00 p.m., comes the Great Change. 

Suddenly you see nothing at all. You do not experience even an expanse of neutral black, as when you clap a hand over closed eyelids. Your visual life becomes suddenly a Nothing, even as the visual life "behind your head" is in your present circumstances a Nothing. (It is not that the human visual field is bounded by an expanse of neutral white or neutral black. No: outside the limited visual field, with its angular width of maybe just 170 or 190 degrees, nothing at all appears.) 

Gone also is the "right-handed being-chilled". Now you have no awareness of cold, or for that matter of warmth, or for that matter of wetness, dryness, or pressure. You likewise have now no feeling of falling, rising, or spinning. Further, you now cease to have sensation-within-the-human-body, such as nausea, or thirst, or the pins-and-needles prickling in some injudiciously immobilized foot.

What you do have is auditory experience, and this you have in astonishing abundance. In your altered state, you note an ensemble of sounds - ringings, buzzings, whistlings, ululations, rumblings, in a variety of pitches and timbres - at times in either soloes or choral plainsong, at other times in harmonies and dissonances, and often with many a diminuendo or crescendo. 

To begin with, I develop this Kaila-Strawson scenario in the starker of its two principal possible forms, in monaural terms. It will later be helpful to consider also a binaural, i.e., a stereophonic, version. Readers with access to an old-fashioned 1960s-through-1990s sitting-room stereo set, equipped with headphones, can appreciate the difference readily. Let the equipment be playing into headphones, whether from CD or from gramophone disk or from FM broadcast, some stereophonic orchestral work. Those old amplifiers or tuner-amplifiers would in at least some instances have a front-panel switch (in the possibly-1967 equipment I myself have inherited from my dear parents, a rocker switch), marked "MONO-STEREO". With headphones on, one can appreciate the difference between the two settings. At "STEREO", the orchestral piece sounds spread out, with the horns perhaps "way over there on the left", the kettledrums perhaps "somewhat over toward the right", the flutes perhaps "immediately in front". At "MONO", by contrast, all the instruments seem to be together in one spot, somewhere inside the skull and equidistant from the ears.

****

The key question facing you, Gentle Reader, from 4:00 p.m. onward, is this: Is something making me ring, buzz, whistle (and so on)? It is impossible to establish either the affirmative answer or the negative answer rigorously, just as you cannot establish rigorously before 4:00 p.m. that there is something (sunlight on grass, or at any rate green light on retina, or at any rate electrochemical disturbance in visual cortex) making you undergo the greening. One recalls from previous weeks the suppositions of Intermittent Furniture and Young Cosmos. Those wicker parlour chairs can coherently, if perhaps perversely and in some sense unreasonably, be envisaged as existing only when inspected. The cosmos - our own human records and human brain memory-traces included - can coherently, if perhaps perversely and in some sense unreasonably, be envisaged as having sprung into existence just two seconds ago.

Analogously, in this week's discussion, then, we have to face the possibility of a perceptual event's occurring without a cause - specifically, the event of your greening, in the scenario prevailing up to 4:00 p.m., and the event of your ringing or booming (or whatever) in the scenario prevailing after 4:00 p.m.

The supposition of an event occurring without a cause would, to be sure, have seemed odd to the Victorian physicists, steeped as they were in Laplacean-Newtonian determinism. Nowadays, however, it must seem less odd. Thanks to popularizing books on quantum mechanics, we are nowadays familiar with the notion of an atomic nucleus's decaying at random:

Here is a rather sinister little thing, a nucleus of polonium-211. It has in some deep and philosophically troubling sense (can some Department of Philosophy specialist in Thomism someday take this further?) a propensity or "potentiality" for radioactive decay. In the particular case of polonium-211, the propensity is stronger than it is for, e.g., the only mildly radioactive uranium-238. For polonium-211, the statistical half-life is short, running to about a half second. We look at this particular nucleus at midnight, and nothing happens. Seven hundred milliseconds elapse. Now the time is 00:00:00.700, and to our mild surprise still nothing has happened. But two hundred milliseconds later, at 00:00:00.900, the looked-for event does happen: the polonium nucleus now emits an alpha particle, decaying "spontaneously" (as the popularizing books say) into a nucleus of the stable isotope lead-207. 

On at any rate the presentations of the popularizing books, which are from considerations of reader-friendliness constrained to gloss over the "hidden variables" (or similar) worries raised by David Bohm (1917-1992), or by similar quantum theorists (I gather that Einstein, opposing Bohr, was in their camp), there is nothing at all causing the nucleus to decay at 00:00:00.900 rather than at 00:00:00.700 or (e.g.) 00:00:00.300. In general, so far as I can see - and the popularizing books on quantum mechanics do help make this palatable - for any event X, it is coherent to suppose that something made X happen, and also coherent to suppose that nothing made X happen. (It is not necessarily, I stress, that the two suppositions are equally reasonable. I insist only that both suppositions are coherent.) We shall embrace the latter supposition if we affirm the counterfactual conditional, "X would have happened no matter what the prior history of the cosmos had been, at least insofar as the supposed prior history is logically consilient with the occurrence of X." (That little caveat about logical consilience is needed to forestall niggling, verbal, quibbles such as this: if X is the final coming-to-rest, at exactly noon, of a soccer ball, then X could not have occurred if the soccer ball had not been moving just before noon. In a trivial, verbal, sense, coming-to-rest, as distinct from being-at-rest, logically requires some previous being-in-motion.) Once we reject the DEFGH analysis of causation (Part C, 2017-05-29/2017-05-30), we must, so far as I can see, accept this counterfactual supposition as coherent - regarding it as unlike the (incoherent) supposition that we have drawn a four-sided triangle or have met a married bachelor.

It will help some readers if I add that my remark about X possibly-occurring-without-a-cause has a parallel in propositions of the form "Every P-event is accompanied by a Q-event." The cosmos abounds in such "P-Q" regularities. (Here is one: whenever two massive spherical bodies are placed in proximity to each other, then - in the absence of special restraining forces, such as would be exerted by restraining harnesses or other mechanical supports - the bodies accelerate toward each other, with this acceleration directly proportional to the product of their masses and inversely proportional to the square of the separation of their centres.) Once we reject the DEFGH analysis of causation, we must regard "P-Q" regularities as subject not to one possible interpretation, but to two equally coherent (albeit not necessarily equally reasonable) interpretations: perhaps (i) the "P-Q" regularity is a law; perhaps, on the other hand, (ii) the regularity is a mere accidental coincidence, a so-to-speak astonishing run of luck in the cosmic casino. Where the regularity is a matter of law, there is something underlying which, if only we were to become privy to it, would explain the observed "P-Q" coincidences; where, on the other hand, the regularity is a mere accidental coincidence, there is nothing underlying (so to speak, nothing more to be known). - For more than two centuries after Newton, the gravitational regularity which I have cited as my example was presumed non-accidental, and yet nobody had any idea what underlay it. (Newton, in particular, prudently wrote that he was himself calculating the direction and magnitude of the empirically manifest gravitational accelerations without "forming any hypotheses" regarding their underlying nature -  Hypotheses non fingo.) Then, in the time of World War 1, a possible explanation was put forward in the Theory of General Relativity.  (General Relativity considers gravitation to be a manifestation of curvature in spacetime. The theory makes some predictions in observational astronomy, and these have so far been borne out).

Further, dark, philosophical questions loom here, in my weasel-word "underlying": are, for instance, P-Q regularities underlain (as I, weasel-like, say) by mere further regularities, or (as I rather guess we should affirm in the case of General Relativity) by something in some subtle way possessing more explanatory power than mere further regularities? Much though I would like to be able to write further on the dark questions, I have not studied enough physics to be able to launch the project. 

I now recapitulate: upon rejecting, as I do urge we reject, the DEFGH analysis of causation, we can for any event X coherently both (a) say "Maybe nothing made X happen" and (b) say "Maybe something made X happen". We can say this pair of things no matter how disparate the two competing sayings may be in their respective intrinsic plausibility or reasonableness.

In particular, then, I am today, as a corollary of my underlying, nonreductionist, "realist", anti-DEFGH, philosophy-of-causation, insisting that you can entertain, as a coherent supposition in the case of the after-4:00-p.m. Kaila-Strawson auditory scenario, the supposition that something is making you ring (buzz, warble, boom, whistle, rumble, ululate, ... ). On this coherently entertainable supposition, it is inevitably the case that you are hearing something in ringing, are hearing something in buzzing, and so on. Once given this so-coherent supposition, it ineluctably follows that you are hearing a thing which is making you ring (or buzz, or whatever) - just as you were before 4:00 p.m. seeing a sunlit lawn (and a municipal neighbourhood, and an optic-nerve event, and so on) that was making you "do some greening", and were before 4:00 p.m. feeling some cold glass (and cold finger flesh, and sequence of neuronal events) that was making you "be-chilled".

To make these ideas more clear, it will help to explore, for a moment, the connection between causation and counterfactuals.

If something is after 4:00 p.m. making you "do some rumbling", as the illumination of the lawn by sunlight is before 4:00 p.m. making you "do some greening", then the following counterfactuals are true:

  • There is before 4:00 p.m. something x, logically distinct from the event of your "greening", such that were x not to exist-or-occur, you would not be "greening". 
  • There is after 4:00 p.m. something x, logically distinct from the event of your "rumbling", such that were x not to exist-or-occur, you would not be "rumbling". 
So much, then, for counterfactuals.  Continuing now with my main theme, I note the arising of two sub-possibilities, both of them again inevitably coherent:

- (b.a) The various things you hear in ringing (roaring, warbling, ululating, etc) - the thing, or the various things, that are making you undergo what you are undergoing - exist only when you are roaring (warbling, ululating, etc).

- (b.b) Some of the various things you hear in ringing (roaring, warbling, ululating, etc) exist even at one or more times at which you happen not to be roaring (warbling, ululating, etc).


Here, as with the competing suppositions of Persistent and Intermittent Furniture (Part C, 2017-05-29/2017-05-30, with also a small clarification and expansion in Part E, 2017-06-19/2017-06-20), I do not assert my competing choices to be equally reasonable. - For the rest of this week's discussion, I fix on supposition (b.b), without troubling to consider what conceivable embellishments of the scenario would render (b.b) more reasonable than (b.a).

Under (b.b) are three possible cases: 

(1) After 4:00 p.m., you continue to reside in the familiar-physics cosmos of baryonic matter, arranged in space. This is now, however, a cosmos whose appearance to you is altered. No longer does a sunlit lawn appear to you a certain way through looking to you a certain way: rather, it appears to you in a certain (novel) way through sounding to you in a certain way. (Perhaps you are hearing the sunlit lawn in so steadily and gently rumbling, and are hearing some other things - a nearby red tablecloth, for example - in at the same time keening. It will be a little like the scenario under heading "I" from Part G (2017-07-10/2017-07-11), in which people are feeling a straightforwardly baryonic-physics thing, the nozzle-released gas, in Sicking at First Avenue and B Street.)

(2) After 4:00 p.m., you reside in some altogether new cosmos.

Possibility (2) divides into two subpossibilities, thereby yielding the just-mentioned total of three cases:

(2.1) Perhaps, as you hearken carefully, all your efforts at discerning a systematic phenomenology are in vain. Try as you will to discern patterns in your warblings, your ululations, and the like, your efforts bear scant fruit. Here you could, admittedly, stubbornly regard yourself as inhabiting a cosmos of baryonic, or perhaps nonbaryonic, matter, arranged in space - and yet it might now be equally, or more, reasonable to start regarding yourself as inhabiting a novel cosmos of things-in-time-without-space.

(2.2) Perhaps, as you hearken carefully over the hours, days, weeks, and years, a rich systematic phenomenology does come to your notice. Here it might, depending on the details of the systematization, be specially reasonable for you to posit not only that you are in a now-exotic, probably non-baryonic, cosmos of things capable of persisting-even-when-unheard, but that your cosmos has even a spatial structure. Diligent hearkening might eventually make it possible to say something about the probable nature of the space - as comprising, perhaps, some finite number of dimensions; and as being either (A) finite with (say) the topology of a sphere, or again the topology of a torus, or (B) infinite; and as possessing some definite geometry (as being everywhere of finite constant positive curvature, perhaps; or as being everyone classically Euclidean, i.e., as being everywhere of zero curvature; or as varying in curvature, with the curvature of space perhaps even zero in some localities, and positive in others, and negative in yet others).

We have so far considered only monaural "soundings" (monaural "auditory undergoings", or - to switch for a moment to a language a little different from, and yet neither superior to nor inferior to our language so far - "acoustic appearances"). Let us now, however, briefly move that so-to-speak front-panel rocker switch to its "STEREO" setting. The "STEREO" effect is one way, although not the only way, of developing a phenomenology so rich as to support option (2.2), or even the particularly consoling option (1):

Just before the 4:00 p.m. Great Transformation in how you were living, there was a table to your left, with a bright red cloth. On the sunlit lawn in front of you a crow was slowly approaching, at that moment striding rather than flying. Now, immediately after 4:00 p.m., you note to your so-to-speak-stereo-headphones left a shrill, steady keening, and in front of you a low, equally steady, rumble. Superimposed on these is a rather pleasant bassoon sound, with a melodic line suggesting dignified strolling. The line is a bit like the gallery-strolling theme which punctuates Mussorgsky's piano suite "Pictures at an Exhibition". This melodic line gets gradually louder, as though some orchestra bassoonist was approaching you. You might well take the keening to be "the way the tablecloth now appears",  the rumble to be "the way the grass now appears", and the agreeable  modestpetrovitshmussorgskilik melody to be "the way the striding, approaching crow now appears". (This is how one class of adjectives gets formed in Estonian: "effessbeelik" for "of or pertaining to the FSB" - here of course the "ee" is as in German "Jena", not as in English "jeep" - "essveeärrlik" for "of or pertaining to the SVR", "tsaristlik" for "Czarist (of or pertaining to the Tsar)", and "modestpetrovitshmussorgskilik" for "of or pertaining to Модест Петрович Мусоргский".)

****

Now I must depart in a mild way from my generally-to-be-respected Igominy and Humiligation Precept, as promulgated in Part B (2017-05-22/2017-05-23). I must do this so as to maximize the probability of some blogspot reader's linking my own ideas up, in some eventually fruitful way, with the ideas of the current, 2017-era, Department of Philosophy professionals. (I have at all points in this year's philosophy-writing project to manoeuvre between competing desiderata. In this present instance, the Precept, insistent though it is, needs to be subordinated to still more insistent considerations regarding probable benefits to readers in one or another Department of Philosophy.)

In his 1970s lectures, the Oxford philosopher Gareth Evans foreshadowed an important, I think then-upcoming, project of his, his "General Theory of Objects". I rather think it was in the course of this foreshadowing that he made his commendatory remark on "transcendental investigations, such as those conducted by Mr [or perhaps by then already Prof.?] Strawson". Prof. Strawson had of course in his 1959 book Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics and his 1966 book The Bounds of Sense been drawing on some Prussian or other, working over in Kaliningrad some five generations before the Red Army totally smashed Kaliningrad up - Prof. Immanuel Tank, or something, in some kind of celebrated Kritik der Reinen Etwas. One gleaned from the youngish Mr Evans's reference to "trascendental investigations" (and still more of transcendental investigations being "conducted") a delicious vision of silver-haired Principal Investigator Prof. Sir Peter Strawon, chevrons on dark sleeve, behind a row of desk telephones: "Yes, do let me assure you, Madam - our investigations here at the Yard are well in hand."

Somebody, in some Department of Philosophy somewhere or other, might some day be reading not only these present cringe-worthy blogspot materials, but also the Nachlass of the eminent, universally mourned, Gareth Evans. I do think that some posthumously published work of Mr Evans, on the specific Kaila-Strawson theme, does exist, somewhere. I at any rate recall Mr Evans, gesticulating in his lecture, I imagine under the theatrical influence of Wittgenstein. (A philosophical friend and I called Mr Evans "Gazzers" behind his back. "Gazzers" for his part rightly admired, as my friend and I were perhaps occasionally liable to put it, "Witters".) Mr Evans emitted what to my untutored ear sounded like Wittgensteinean, or any any rate Teutonic, phonemes, mixing his metaphors deftly amid the gesticulations:

Phenomenalism ACHHHHHH ... phenomenalism AKHHHHHH! ... PHENOMENALISM! - is a horse ... that is often flogged ... but seldom understood. 

Without digging in libraries, I cannot myself say what the official "Gazzers" line on phenomenalism was, though I am sure it was something deep. I do commend such library work to my readers. The normal crude Tallahassee Swampwater Junior Training College line, which I think Mr Evans was deprecating, runs as follows, for what little it is worth:

Confronted with my purely auditory undergoings - my auditory sense data, my auditory Vorstellungen - I deploy semantic manoeuvres to assemble my auditory undergoings into a language of physical objects. The physical objects are not fundamental realities, but mere "logical constructions" out of those truly fundamental things which are my sense-data. 

What my blog postings are herewith offering, or are at least herewith groping toward, is an alternative:

Confronted with my purely auditory undergoings (the "acoustic appearances") - for instance with my soft-and-steady roaring, with my equally steady keening, with my bassoon-like crescendo modestpetrovitschmussorgskilik melody line - I recognize the logically coherent possibility that in roaring, keening, and the like I am hearing a cosmos of physical objects - perhaps a nonspatial cosmos; perhaps a fully spatial cosmos; perhaps even a spatial cosmos of familiar-physics baryonic matter, arranged into such familiar things as a lawn, a tablecloth, and a crow. 

This alternative, namely that you (as "Gentle Reader") are hearing physical objects in buzzing, keening, warbling (etc), is forced on us as soon as

  • we accept a realist, as opposed to a reductionist "DEFG" (Part C, 2017-05-29/2017-05-30) semantic analysis of causation;
  • we note that just as in the philosophy of action, so too in the philosophy of perception there is, for many an X and Y, "X-ing in Y-ing"; 
  • we note the conceptual legitimacy of projections, as sketched in the 1950s or earlier by Wittgenstein, in some celebrated passage of his on pain - for Wittgenstein, "pain-patches on a leaf", and for us here at blogspot in the similarly projective locution "I feel a Pain at First Avenue and A Street in hurting" (and, although the actual historic 1920s-through-1950s Prof. Wittgenstein did not write this, "I am feeling the Sick at First Avenue and B Street in sicking," and again "I am seeing the lawn in 'greening'," and again "I am feeling the ice-chilled beverage glass in being-chilled").
Is any alternative - any duly articulable philosophical "phenomenalism", going beyond the level of sloganeering Tallahassee Swampwater sciolism - possible at all, once we do the three just-listed things? I do not see it. But perhaps Mr Evans's published Nachlass, somewhere, achieves some deep appraisal of phenomenalism more favourable than what I have myself been able to produce in this year's blogging.

[This pretty much concludes what has proved to be a surprisingly protracted discussion of perception. In at least the latter part of my next installment, I hope to embark on a discussion - I hope less protracted - of action. I hope to be still sticking rather closely to the project outline I offered in three "fragments" toward the end of Part B, back on 2017-05-22/2017-05-23. That upcoming installment probably cannot be uploaded next week, when blogging will have to touch on other themes altogether (and to be perhaps unusually brief). I do, however, hope to be uploading it at some point in the next two or three weeks.]





Monday 24 July 2017

Toomas Karmo: Part I: Perception, Action, and "Subjectivity"

Quality assessment:



On the 5-point scale current in Estonia, and surely in nearby nations, and familiar to observers of the academic arrangements of the late, unlamented, Union of Soviet Socialist Republics (applying the easy and lax standards Kmo deploys in his grubby imaginary "Aleksandr Stepanovitsh Popovi nimeline sangarliku raadio instituut" (the "Alexandr Stepanovitch Popov Institute of Heroic Radio") and his  grubby imaginary "Nikolai Ivanovitsh Lobatshevski nimeline sotsalitsliku matemaatika instituut" (the "Nicolai Ivanovich Lobachevsky Institute of Socialist Mathematics") - where, on the lax and easy grading philosophy of the twin Institutes, 1/5 is "epic fail", 2/5 is "failure not so disastrous as to be epic", 3/5 is "mediocre pass", 4/5 is "good", and 5/5 is "excellent"): 4/5. Justification: There was enough time to write out the  necessary points to reasonable length.


Revision history:


All times in these blog "revision histories" are stated in UTC (Universal Coordinated Time/ Temps Universel Coordoné,  a precisification of the old GMT, or "Greenwich Mean Time"), in the ISO-prescribed YYYYMMDDThhmmZ timestamping format. UTC currently leads Toronto civil time by 4 hours and currently lags Tallinn civil time by 3 hours.

  • 20170725T1446Z/version 3.0.0: Kmo finished converting his polished outline into full-sentences prose. He now started a minor process of inspection and revision. He reserved the right to make minor, nonsubstantive, purely cosmetic, revisions over the coming 48 hours, as here-undocumented versions 3.0.1, 3.0.2, 3.0.3, ... . 
  • 20170725T0333Z/version 2.0.0: Kmo managed to upload a polished outline. He now intended to get to bed, and after breakfast to start converting his outline into complete-sentences prose. He continued to think that it would be possible to finish the conversion by UTC=20170725T2000Z.
  • 20170725T0001Z/version 1.0.0: Running a full half-day behind schedule, Kmo had time only to upload a rough outline. He hoped by UTC=20170725T0401Z to have converted this into a polished outline, and by UTC=20170725T2000Z to have finished converting the rough outline into complete-sentences prose.


[CAUTION: A bug in the blogger server-side software has in some past months shown a propensity to insert inappropriate whitespace at some points in some of my posted essays. If a screen seems to end in empty space, keep scrolling down. The end of the posting is not reached until the usual blogger "Posted by Toomas (Tom) Karmo at" appears. - The blogger software has also shown a propensity, at any rate when coupled with my erstwhile, out-of-date, Web-authoring uploading browser, to generate HTML that gets formatted in different ways on different downloading browsers. Some downloading browsers have sometimes perhaps not correctly read in the entirety of the "Cascading Style Sheets"  (CSS) which on all ordinary Web servers control the browser placement of margins, sidebars, and the like. If you suspect CSS problems in your particular browser, be patient: it is probable that while some content has been shoved into some odd place (for instance, down to the bottom of your browser, where it ought to appear in the right-hand margin), all the server content has been pushed down into your browser in some place or other. - Finally, there may be blogger vagaries, outside my control, in font sizing or interlinear spacing or right-margin justification. - Anyone inclined to help with trouble-shooting, or to offer other kinds of technical advice, is welcome to write me via Toomas.Karmo@gmail.com.]


I have been considering how you (the "Gentle Reader") see one thing in seeing another - seeing, for instance, the municipal neighbourhood in seeing the sunlit grass, and seeing the sunlit grass in seeing a visual-cortex event (an event with a subtle microstructure, perhaps not yet too well mapped by physiology). I have noted that the so-to-speak "sequence of seeings" - seeing something in seeing another thing, seeing that other thing in seeing yet another - has a rather distinctive ultimate term. I have indulged in a neologism, calling this ultimate term your "greening" (by analogy with your "hurting" or your "thirsting"). 

This week I note that the ultimate term could be described differently, and less neologistically. Questions of neologism aside, this week's alternative description is neither superior nor inferior to my description from the two previous installments. 

For you to be greening, I note this week, is for something to be "appearing (specifically, looking) a certain way to you" (looking, in fact, "grassy", or again "green" - there is more than one natural-sounding adjective here). 

Two weeks ago, I suggested, in the neologistic parlance of "greening", that there is no sense in which your "greening" either colour-matches or colour-mismatches the grass. Last week I ended with the suggestion that there is nothing special about colour - that there is nothing here which does not equally apply to left-handed and right-handed shapes, and to spatial orientation. (There is no sense in which - to recall last week's example - as you behold the top-dimpled wooden R and the top-dimpled wooden Cyrillic Ya (the letter я), on their respective squares of wool and linen on the lawn, your "R-ing" shape-matches or shape-mismatches either the R or the Ya, or in which your "Ya-ing" either shape-matches or shape-mismatches either the R or the Ya.) These suggestions can be developed also for this week's alternative language, of "looking" or "appearing", as follows:

  • There is no one way green grass ought to look. The imagined Paleolithic diet from two weeks ago changes the look of grass to you, and yet cannot be said either to make the grass "now look the way it is supposed to look" or to make the grass "now look other than the way it is supposed to look". 
  • There is no one pair of ways in which the R and the Ya are respectively supposed to look. The imagined intonation, from last week, of the mystic words "Minu-isa-oli-pottsepp-ja-kandis-valge-hobusega-LIIIva" changes the look of the R and the Ya, and yet cannot be said to make either of these two wooden letters "now look the way they ought to look", or to make them "now look the reverse of the way they ought to look".
****
If it is granted that we see the grass in seeing each of the various terms in a sequence of events within the human body, it may still be asked, "Does some special epistemic status attach to the seeing of the grass? Could it be that the seeing of the grass is in some sense a 'Direct Seeing', or a 'Basic Seeing', or something of this kind, with the seeing of the retinal patch-of-light and the seeing of the optic-nerve event and the seeing of the cortical event in some contrasting sense instances of 'Non-Basic Seeing'?" The (substantial?) minority of my readership who have a training in university-campus philosophy will recall that in the 1960s, 1970s, or 1980s analytical philosophy of action, stress was placed on "Basic Actions". Perhaps - for all that I can now recall of that philosophical literature, as I read in it some decades ago - there was a specially direct connection with an agent's intention in the case of those of his actions which qualified as "Basic". 

But I suggest this week - admittedly with hesitation and unease - that any sense in which the seeing of the grass is "Basic" or "Fundamental" or "Specially Privileged" is contingent, lacking philosophical significance. It seems to me to be a mere sociological or medical matter, and not a philosophical matter, that we present-day humans have a propensity to conceptualize ourselves as seeing grass, and on the other hand have difficulty in conceptualizing ourselves as seeing retinal, optic-nerve, and cerebral-cortex events. Our identifications of the various things we are seeing depend in a merely banal way on our upbringing and our present practical needs. There is not much present practical advantage, for the ordinary human in the present ordinary social world, in conceptualizing the various things that are occurring at the level of the retina, optic nerve, and visual cortex. It is, on the other hand, presently of eminent practical advantage for humans to know that they are a few metres away from a patch of living grass, as opposed to an expanse of red-hot coals. 

Consider a dystopian science-fiction scenario in which humans get farmed on this planet by extraterrestrial invaders, rather as certain aphids are farmed by certain ants. No longer do humans run around under the open skies, rejoicing in expanses of sunlit lawn: no, they are fastened to harnesses in the depths of great anthills, serving the malign purposes of their eerie new masters. Human survival priorities are now such as to make humans quickly learn what events are happening on their retinal surfaces or in their neurons, as they strive to placate their alien overlords. Some few humans, fortunate enough to be accorded scientific educations and be conducted in their harnesses out of the anthill on "field trips", do eventually take an informed interest in the botany of sunlit landscapes, on the far side of their corneas. 

It is, to be sure, hard to imagine how such humans would speak, whether with each other or with their alien overlords. I suppose they would have a vocabulary different from our own - describing, somehow, in rich and detailed terms hard for us to envision at all, events in the visual cortex, and finding the language of external-to-cortex "sunlight" and "grass" to be as recondite and technical as we ourselves find the language of behind-the-cornea synapses and dendra. With hesitancy and trepidation, I do suggest that this inversion of what might be thought the natural order of language - the only order we, in our rather happy present unfettered condition, know - is coherent. 

A second, related, point seems again to be a matter of mere medical contingencies. 

It might, for all I know, be that humans have some kind of special hard-wired, instinctual propensity for taking the "thing most evidently seen" to be grass in front of the cornea, as distinct from a neuronal event behind the cornea. It would be a little like the instinctual propensity to take a certain feeling of dryness in the throat as a signal that the body would now benefit from drinking water. Even this, for all I can see this week (I write hesitantly, subject to correction), is a mere medical matter, lacking philosophical significance. I look at it as follows: What is a matter of instinct could in most cases in principle be learned; and conversely, what is learned could in principle be a matter of instinct; and so the difference between what "comes instinctually" and what "has to be learned" is philosophically irrelevant. Can we not imagine someone being born with even an instinctual understanding of a language? Or with even an instinctual grasp of a complex practical matter, such as the way to buy groceries on a bank's debit card (with even knowledge of the password being happily innate)? Why could humans not be born in the way birds are hatched, with most or all of our practical routines - with even such elaborate human accomplishments as language use, and the use of money - already in place? It is at any rate striking how the infant bird seems to know, without instruction, how to hold its beak open and vertical for the incoming, parentally supplied, meal, and how adult birds seem to know how to emit their territorial and mating calls - I presume as instinctively as they know how to catch insects, or how to dry-bathe themselves in a patch of roadside dust.

****

The various points I have developed for visual perception apply also to the other perceptual modalities.

The hearing of a bell proceeds as follows:

  • one hears the bell in hearing air vibrate
  • one hears the air vibrate in hearing an eardrum vibrate
  • one hears the eardrum vibrate in hearing the three middle-ear bones vibrate
  • one hears those bones vibrate in hearing the cochlear fluid vibrate
  • one hears the cochlear fluid vibrate in hearing electrical activity in an auditory nerve
  • one hears the auditory-nerve activity in hearing activity in the auditory cortex
  • one hears activity in the auditory cortex (not in hearing oneself ringing, but more simply) in so-to-speak "ringing" (where "I am ringing" is a neologism parallel to "I am thirsting", "I am hurting", and the neologistic "I am greening": to say "I am hearing the ringing", in this present sense of "ringing", is a category-mistake, parallel to "I am seeing the greening")
To the objection that nerve activity is not in normal parlance heard, the reply is simply, "Well, I for my part don't hear your nerve activity. But I do hear mine. The situation parallels fullness of stomach. I do not feel the fullness of your stomach, after we have shared a heavy breakfast, and yet I do feel the fullness of my stomach." We might also reply to this objection that talk of hearing cortical events would become natural enough in, e.g., a world in which the aurora borealis triggered resonances in the cortex: "We got a bright aurora over the farm last night; my brain was ringing so loudly that I could hardly finish evening chores."

Similarly, the feeling of a pig-wrapped-in-a-blanket proceeds as follows:

  • one feels the pig in feeling the blanket
  • one feels the blanket in feeling pressure on one's skin 
  • one feels pressure on one's skin in feeling events in nerves, running from hand out to spinal cord and up into skull
  • one feels the nerve events in feeling a cortical event
  • one feels the cortical event (not in feeling "pressured", but) in being-pressured - where "I am pressured" is once again a neologism analogous to "I am thirsting", "I am hurting", and the neologistic "I am greening" 
****

I leave it as an assignment to predict what will have to be said in the next installment - one or two or three or so weeks from now - regarding the Kaila-Strawson "sound universe". Although I must on the whole respect my Igominy and Humiligation Precept, as laid out in Part B (2017-05-22 or 2017-05-23), nevertheless it will in this present instance help people to get a couple of serious citations from me. So be aware of some literature, folks: a Finnish philosopher, Eino Kaila (1890-1958) developed, I think a few years before the Hitler war - in more locally Finnish terms, a few years before the 1939-1940 Winter War - the idea of a conscious subject in a universe which in some sense "consisted merely of sounds". Prof. Kaila's idea was later picked up in Britain by Peter (in due course Prof. Sir Peter) Strawson (1919-2006), in his 1959 book Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics. I know of Prof. Kaila because not Prof. Strawson alone, but Strawson-plus-Kaila, got examined in a lecture which I heard in Oxford, perhaps around 1976 or 1977, from University College philosopher Gareth Evans (1946-1980).

Without having Kaila or Strawson immediately to hand, I this week simply sketch their idea. You (the "Gentle Reader") see nothing, feel nothing, and smell and taste nothing. And yet you hear a great deal. You hear sounds in various suggestive crescendos and dimuendos, with also suggestively systematic changes in pitch and timbre, both in plainsong and in polyphony. You hear sounds that might tempt you to map out a spatial world of sounds. (Has space a real meaning in the Kaila-Strawson setting? This is a question to be examined.) There are even persistent sounds that might be "revisited", as one might revisit the same sunlit lawn from one afternoon to the next. (To what extent, however, are we entitled to speak of "revisiting", and of "sounds existing, or occurring, where I do not hear them", and the like? Again, these are questions to be examined.) There are even specially persistent sounds that you might be tempted to identify as "my body, or me myself, moving through the sound universe, first visiting Sound X, then departing from Sound X, then returning to Sound X". (Again, these are questions here to be examined: is it the case that I have a body - in this secnario, perhaps "a sound" - or, rather, that I am a body?)

How, in terms of the framework being developed here, is such a Kaila-Strawson sound universe to be regarded? How do we fit into the present framework the absence from this universe of anything very evidently corresponding to atmosphere, eardrum, middle-ear bones, cochlear fluid, and auditory cortex?

In working the assignment, readers might want to review my remarks on the Pain and the Sick, from Part G (2017-07-10 or 2017-07-11), asking themselves to what extent the scenarios which I there label "I", "IIa", and "IIb" have parallels in the Kaila-Strawson setting.

[This is the end of the current blog posting.]




Sunday 23 July 2017

Ary Scheffer et al.: Saint Augustine and Saint Monica: A Short Reflection

An oil-on-canvas (I think) reproduction, hanging in the Marylake retreat centre in the Archdiocese of Toronto, of a painting by Dutch-French Romantic artist Ary Scheffer (1795-1858). The painting conveys on the one side the validity of human affection (as communicated in the linked hands) and on the other side the power of divine love (the object of the common gaze of the two Saints - directed to things outside the frame of the canvas, and yet foreshadowed within the canvas by two emblems of eternity, the tranquil sea and the tranquil sky).   

Monday 17 July 2017

Toomas Karmo: More Study Aids for Biblical Hebrew

One of the five or so desktops in my current Debian GNU/Linux 9.0 ("stretch", in the "current stable" branch). Clockwise from upper left: operations clocks (green for local Ontario civil time, red for UTC (Coordinated Universal Time)); a browser shot from one of the various fine YouTube renditions of Yerushalayim shel Zahav (this one is "Jerusalem of Gold - Land Of Promise", by YouTube user "Jewish National Fund", from 2009-12-04, to a length of 3:20, in my corner of the Web under URL https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=BPv6DwoPLt0&index=1&list=RDBPv6DwoPLt0); a Debian GNU/Linux /usr/bin/xterm window judiciously configured to display some of my private notes on Hebrew-language resources; a small display of Current Hebrew Gear in my flat; a browser shot from the YouTube rendition of a Pirates of Penzance  philological parody ("I Am the Very Model of a Biblical Philologist", by YouTube user "Josh Tyra", from 2014-12-11, to a length of 3:44, in my corner of the Web under URL https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=3x2SvqhfevE&t=73s). - The Current Hebrew Gear on display comprises my new Hebrew lexicon, with some handwritten flash cards, and additionally the "Basket of Shame" and "Bowl of Hope".  In the Basket of Shame live some of the Pratico-and-Van Pelt vocabulary flash cards which are currently giving me some trouble. In the Bowl of Hope live those vocabulary cards which I seem for the moment to have mastered. - Josh Tyra's song seems to be (rightly) celebrated among students of Hebrew, even as Prof. Tom Lehrer's Lobachevsky Song must be celebrated among students of mathematics. "I dream in Aramaic and interpret it in Syriac," proclaims this vocalist, adding that he can "mumble in Mandaic and hum a little Hurrian" and "tell a surplice from a chasuble or maniple./ And reconstruct the library of ancient Assurbanipal". Particularly fine is his conjecture regarding the probable geographical origin of the Philistines. - Moving though the "Jewish National Fund" "Yerushalayim shel Zahav" rendition is, I would additionally urge everyone to seek out Ofra Haza's still more moving rendition of this same song, in part for its haunting evocation of  modern Hebrew phonetics: search in YouTube under "Ofra Haza Yerushalayim shel Sahav", or try the link https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=JH8gtdDA5x0.) - The image can be enlarged by mouse-clicking.

Toomas Karmo: Part H: Perception, Action, and "Subjectivity"


Quality assessment:



On the 5-point scale current in Estonia, and surely in nearby nations, and familiar to observers of the academic arrangements of the late, unlamented, Union of Soviet Socialist Republics (applying the easy and lax standards Kmo deploys in his grubby imaginary "Aleksandr Stepanovitsh Popovi nimeline sangarliku raadio instituut" (the "Alexandr Stepanovitch Popov Institute of Heroic Radio") and his  grubby imaginary "Nikolai Ivanovitsh Lobatshevski nimeline sotsalitsliku matemaatika instituut" (the "Nicolai Ivanovich Lobachevsky Institute of Socialist Mathematics") - where, on the lax and easy grading philosophy of the twin Institutes, 1/5 is "epic fail", 2/5 is "failure not so disastrous as to be epic", 3/5 is "mediocre pass", 4/5 is "good", and 5/5 is "excellent"): 4/5. Justification: There was enough time to write out the  necessary points to reasonable length.


Revision history:


All times in these blog "revision histories" are stated in UTC (Universal Coordinated Time/ Temps Universel Coordoné,  a precisification of the old GMT, or "Greenwich Mean Time"), in the ISO-prescribed YYYYMMDDThhmmZ timestamping format. UTC currently leads Toronto civil time by 4 hours and currently lags Tallinn civil time by 3 hours.

  • 20170718T0251Z/version 2.0.0: Kmo finished converting his point-form outline into coherent full-sentences prose. He started a process of polishing. He reserved the right to upload tiny, nonsubsantive, purely cosmetic tweaks over the coming 48 hours, as here-undocumented versions 2.0.1, 2.0.2, 2.0.3, ... . 
  • 20170718T0002Z/version 1.0.0: Kmo uploaded a moderately polished point-form outline. He hoped over the coming 3 hours to convert this into coherent full-sentences prose.

[CAUTION: A bug in the blogger server-side software has in some past months shown a propensity to insert inappropriate whitespace at some points in some of my posted essays. If a screen seems to end in empty space, keep scrolling down. The end of the posting is not reached until the usual blogger "Posted by Toomas (Tom) Karmo at" appears. - The blogger software has also shown a propensity, at any rate when coupled with my erstwhile, out-of-date, Web-authoring uploading browser, to generate HTML that gets formatted in different ways on different downloading browsers. Some downloading browsers have sometimes perhaps not correctly read in the entirety of the "Cascading Style Sheets"  (CSS) which on all ordinary Web servers control the browser placement of margins, sidebars, and the like. If you suspect CSS problems in your particular browser, be patient: it is probable that while some content has been shoved into some odd place (for instance, down to the bottom of your browser, where it ought to appear in the right-hand margin), all the server content has been pushed down into your browser in some place or other. - Finally, there may be blogger vagaries, outside my control, in font sizing or interlinear spacing or right-margin justification. - Anyone inclined to help with trouble-shooting, or to offer other kinds of technical advice, is welcome to write me via Toomas.Karmo@gmail.com.]




My various "Precepts" from Part B of this multi-installment essay, back on 2017-05-22 or 2017-05-23, were driven in large part by the desire to avoid miscommunication. In writing philosophy, as in writing software documentation, one is mindful of a goal which I understand to have been urged already in classical antiquity, by Marcus Fabius Quintilianus (A.D. 35 - A.D. 100):  Do not seek to communicate so as to be understood. Seek, rather, to communicate in such a way as to be incapable of being misunderstood.

I return to last week's example of seeing green grass, in the joint spirit of the Precepts and of Quintillian spelling everything out again. In doing so, I make 100-percent explicit a few things that were in my previous attempt at exposition, a week ago, just 90-percent or 95-percent explicit. I reiterate, and amplify a little, in two stages, which I number herewith.

(1) As you (the "Gentle Reader") gaze upon sunlit lawn, various things are happening:

  • You are seeing the municipal neighbourhood in seeing the garden.
  • You are seeing the garden in seeing the lawn. 
  • You are seeing the lawn in seeing the grass.
  • You are seeing the grass in seeing a small patch of light upon your retina, cast on the retinal surface by a natural (a ray-converging, and consequently an inverting) lens, situated just inside your cornea. (You might, to be sure, be seeing that patch of light without recognizing that it is among the various things you see. Analogously, Prof. Plum, when striking Colonel Mustard dead with the lead wrench in the conservatory, might get seen without getting recognized.) 
  • You are seeing the small patch of light in seeing a certain event in your optic nerve. (This is an event of a kind not known to the Renaissance anatomist-physiologists, whose inquiries pretty much ended with the retina. The event was, on the other hand, surely known to the physiologists of the early 20th century,  equipped as they surely were with equipment for investigating the electrical behaviour of nerves, including nerves within mammalian heads. Again, this is an event that might get seen without getting recognized.) 
  • You are seeing the event in your optic nerve in seeing a certain event in your visual cortex. (This is an event perhaps not fully mapped even by 21st-century physiology, and therefore an event still more liable to get seen without getting recognized.) 
  • You are seeing the event in your visual cortex in greening. 
(2) Seeing-in is transitive, in the sense that for all lambda, mu, and nu, if you see mu in seeing lambda and see nu in seeing mu, then you see nu in seeing lambda. So, in particular, all the following things, and many others like them, are happening:

  • You are seeing the municipal neighbourhood in seeing the grass.
  • You are seeing the garden in seeing the patch of light on the retina.
  • You are seeing the grass in seeing the event in the visual cortex.
  • You are seeing the garden in greening. 
  • You are seeing the grass in greening. 
  • You are seeing the patch of light on the retina in greening. 
  • You are seeing the event in the optic nerve in greening. 
**** 

In some later installment or installments of this essay, I shall have to comment in one or more ways on the special character of the ultimate, and clearly rather special, term I have identified in the perceptual sequence, namely the greening (where "greening" is something we undergo, as we undergo hurting, hungering, thirsting, or being-nauseous ("sicking")). Already tonight, one small supplementary comment, of a cautionary character, has to be made. The greening is not a thing seen in the sense in which all the other various things - the neuronal events, the light on the retina, the grass, the garden, the municipal neighbourhood - are seen. One sees the grass (and so on) in greening, and yet does not see the grass in seeing the greening. To speak of seeing the greening, in the sense in which one sees public objects like grass and retinal illuminations and neuronal events, is to commit what postwar school-of-Austin-and-Ryle British philosophers used to call a "category mistake" - as when one speaks of buying a price, as opposed to paying a price, or when one speaks of a "high rate of speed" as opposed to a "high rate of change of position" or a "high rate of change of speed".

Lack of due attention to this point is one of the things which tutors in my imagined, and yet only too lifelike,  Tallahassee Swampwater Junior Training College use to help them distinguish an essay deserving a high grade from an essay deserving a lesser grade. (I might remark here that if - as was my own lot, between leaving Britain for Australia in 1978 and having in the Ontario of 1991 the good fortune to get kicked out of academic philosophy - one assigns grades to some tens or hundreds of essays on perception, then students' terminological slides become predictable. I used to write up boilerplate corrections, mindful of the several, or even of the several tens, of students destined all to slip up in the same way, in any one given academic semester. So, late in the evening, grading the thirty-fourth essay from the Dispiriting Pile, I would say in a jaded and world-weary way,  "Ah, now we get the ninth one who is writing of 'seeing sense impressions [or of seeing sense data, or whatever]' in the same way as she or he is writing of 'seeing grass'." And then I would direct my nasty little Cold-War-era computer to print out Boilerplate Corrective Note  G (or H, or whatever - if G was for "seeing sense-impressions", then H was for some different, and yet equally recurrent, problem), for eventual stapling to the essay. When finally handed back to its author, a typical essay would have three or four boilerplate comments from the computer, over and above the necessary red-ink handwritten comments. Working on a university campus gets to be like grading peaches on a packing-house conveyor belt.)

****

For clarity tonight, I also amplify a little last week's story regarding the Paleolithic Diet. For most of the perceptual sequence, questions of match and mismatch are meaningless. (That is the sequence in which - if I might be pardoned for now even reiterating a reiteration - we see nu in seeing mu, and see mu in seeing lambda, and so on and so on - ultimately seeing each of the logically later terms in the sequence (not in seeing the greening, but, I stress) in greening.)

There is no sense in which the grass "colour-matches" or "colour-mismatches" the optic-nerve event, or in which either of these "colour-matches" or "colour-mismatches" the greening. Admittedly, there is one rather banal term in the sequence for which question of colour-match and colour-mismatch do arise. It is perhaps a subliminal awareness of this banal term that might be tempting some people - students of philosophy in their wonted clumsiness, and perhaps even some philosophical authors, down through the decades and centuries- to raise contentless questions of match and mismatch. We can in a banal way ask, "Does the retinal patch of light match or mismatch the grass in colour?" The answer is in a banal way in the affirmative: "Yes, unless the eye is burdened with some pathology, such as a discolouration in the normally clear cornea, or normally clear lens, or normally clear eyeball fluids, the colour of the grass does closely match the colour of that publicly viewable, ophthalmoscope-inspectable, green thing which is the retinal patch-of-light."

Even this, however, is a contingent feature of Homo sapiens vision. Imagine a species of visually aware exotic animals, Ophthalmosaurus kodakii, with a pigmented membrane separating the innermost eyeball fluid from the retina. The chameleon-like, or Kodak-like, membrane changes its tints rapidly,  in a chemical-photography tracking of changes in the viewed scene. One could imagine the membrane assuming something like the colour and light-or-dark aspect of a Kodacolor negative. Placing the animal in front of sunlit grass triggers, perhaps, the formation of reddish pigment in the membrane, while placing it in front of a sunlit tomato-ketchup puddle triggers the formation of greenish pigment. In such a case, one could say, "The image formed by the crystalline lens on the surface of the preretinal membrane matches in colour the various sunlit objects forming the image, and yet the image formed within the membrane systematically mismatches those same objects."

With Homo sapiens, as with the imagined Ophthalmosaurus kodakii, most members of the perceptual sequence still cannot be said either to "match" or to "mismatch" the sunlit object in front of the visually aware anaimal. In particular, the greening of the visually aware Ophthalmosaurus kodakii observer, like the greening of a (visually aware) Homo sapiens observer, cannot be said either to "colour-match" or to "colour-mismatch" the sunlit grass.

****

In "Part G" of this essay, on 2017-07-10 or 2017-07-11, I brought out the impossibility of querying colour-matching and colour-mismatching by telling a story regarding a "Paleolithic Diet". This same story could be developed in other ways. Here is one: you, as the "Gentle Reader", are presented not with the Paleolithic Diet but with shamanic incantations. To your surprise, you find that whenever you intone, in an appropriately scary Uralic manner, "minu-isa-oli-pottsep-ja-kandis-valge-hobusega-LIIIII-va", grass starts looking like ketchup, and ketchup like grass - with things getting back to normal as soon as you stop the intoning. Does the So-Powerful Incantation clear your vision, so that you at last start seeing things "in their true colours", or does it distort your vision? The question lacks content.

Further, this same story can be developed, with the same no-content-to-the-question moral, in terms of intersubjective comparisons. (To be sure, I will have to return to the vast, difficult topic of intersubjectivity in some later installment. Tonight's observation is only a tiny first take, almost a throw-away remark.)

You (the Gentle Reader) and I, as two fellow specimens of Homo sapiens, are together seated at the edge of a sunlit lawn. You have no way of knowing whether my greening is the same as your greening, or on the contrary is the same as your, so to speak, "redding". But suppose (I write tonight briefly, almost as a throw-away) that your greening is indeed like my redding, and your redding indeed like my greening. Then there is no content to the question which of us has "accurate colour vision", and which of us has "systematically distorted colour vision".

The situation parallels a situation with motion duly stressed by Einstein, but treated already by Newton and Galileo. Suppose the cosmos presently, at 12.00 noon, to comprise just two particles, A and B, of negligible mass and negligible electric charge, presently one kilometre apart. Let the two particles move in such a way that their separation diminishes at a steady rate over the next hour, so that by 13.00 they are just one metre apart, with neither particle "subject to a constant-speed acceleration, such as might occur in constant-speed curvilinear motion". (I will take it, without having thought carefully through this perhaps potentially deep question - eventually we do have to ponder at least the scary topic of spinning frames - that we can somehow make rigorous the demand that none of the constant-speed motion be constant-speed curvilinear.) Then for Einstein, Newton, and Galileo alike, there is no content to the question "Which particle was it that really moved?" The only cognitively contentful assessment is a frame-relative assessment: in each rest frame of Particle A, it was Particle B that moved, and in each rest frame of Particle B, it was Particle A that moved.

A similar situation obtains for the Paleolithic Diet (and also, mutatis mutandis, for the shamanic incantation, and for the scenario in which you and I are together on the lawn). With respect to the Post-Paleolithic Diet, it is the Paleolithic Diet that inverts colour vision; and with respect to the Paleolithic Diet, it is the Post-Paleolithic Diet that inverts it; and there is no content to the question, "Which Diet delivers accurate colour vision?"

****

Seven nights ago, I asked whether this frame-relativization principle for colour vision (I quote verbatim) possesses parallels, or on the contrary lacks parallels, in a more basic aspect of human sensory functioning - in the visual perception of mere shapes, and of mere right-left, up-down, orientation. My answer is, "It possesses parallels." (I went on last week to note that - again I quote verbatim -  Some in Departments of Philosophy affirm, following John Locke (1632-1704), that there is a deep logical difference between perception of colour and perception of shape and orientation. Others in Departments of Philosophy deny this. Who, I asked, is right - those who affirm, or those who deny? So tonight I answer, "Those who deny." 

For consider not the difference between sunlit grass and sunlit ketchup, but the difference between the Roman letter R and the final letter of the Russian alphabet, the "Ya" (the я, a "backward R"). Imagine us to have a woollen square and a linen square spread out on the lawn. On the wool is placed a wooden R. On the linen is placed a wooden Ya. To forestall irrelevant complications, let us further imagine that the intended top surface of each wooden letter is marked with a dimple, at the point where the bowl of the letter meets its oblique stroke. (Without the top-surface dimple marker, someone might start quibbling in some way, perhaps, on the basis that a Russian Ya is "merely a Roman R flipped over". With the dimple marker, by contrast, the two wooden letters are three-dimensional mirror reversals of each other, not capable of being brought into superposition by any combination of 3-space (xyz-space) translations and 3-space rotations.)

Suppose now that upon your starting the Paleolothic Diet, or upon your intoning "minu-isa-oli-pottsep-ja-kandis-valge-hobusega-LIIIII-va" (or whatever), the top-dimpled R starts looking to you the way the top-dimpled Ya used to look, and the top-dimpled Ya the way the top-dimpled R used to look. Under which diet (or which vocal régime) were you "seeing shapes accurately"? If no meaningful answer is possible in the case of seeing colour, then equally is no meaningful answer possible in the case of seeing shape.

In terms of some physics and molecular-chemistry literature, the top-dimpled R/top-dimpled Ya difference is one of chirality, or "handedness". This "handedness" example of R and Ya could be developed in various other ways - for instance, by winding two coils from stiff wire, in opposite senses, or indeed by simply laying down on wool and linen, respectively, a bolt with right-handed thread and a bolt with left-handed thread. (In a normal machine shop, bolts tend to have the right-hand thread, as indeed also do normal jars and their normal lids. But left-hand-bolts can be procured.) 

It will be evident how to develop this point also for up-down orientation. The Paleolithic Diet, perhaps, makes the sky suddenly look "down here", the earth suddenly look "up there". This is a different kind of perceptual flip from a chirality-flip.

As far as I can see, the point holds even for visual length comparisons: if the Paleolithic Diet makes circles start looking the way moderately eccentric ellipses used to look, and the moderately eccentric ellipses start looking - depending, I do have to admit, on the orientation of their foci! - either the way circles used to look or the way highly eccentric ellipses used to look , there is no content to the question which dietary régime "makes us see objects in their true shapes". 

[This is the end of the present blog posting. It is hoped that the next installment, "Part I", will appear one or two or three weeks from now.]


_

Monday 10 July 2017

Toomas Karmo: Study Aids for Biblical Hebrew

Study aids for Biblical Hebrew - a philological topic discussed in my "Further to Mr Kaller: Three Theological Shocks" posting of 2017-07-03 or 2017-07-04. From the bottom of the stack upward: the popularizing 1975 Time-Life book on the pre-Exilic Israelites which I had found so helpful the day before I started that blog posting; my Pratico-and-Van Pelt Hebrew grammar, opened to a page rather dense in pencil annotations; a trusty pencil (with  "B" lead; "B" is perhaps more comfortable than the more usual "HB", both for philology and for mathematics-physics); a laminated four-page study aid, summarizing main grammar points (and therefore useful in raising morale: from glancing at the aid, one can not only recall tricky details in paradigms, but also can accurately gauge how much of the language is already learned, and how much of it remains terra incognita); a trusty evening cuppa. Not shown is a book which I hope to pick up this week from theology shop Crux, on the University of Toronto campus, and which I already last week asked Crux to set aside for me, awaiting pickup  -  W.L. Holladay's Concise Hebrew and Aramaic Lexicon of the Old Testament (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1988). It appears from reader reviews that Holladay is an appropriate first lexicon. The Hebrew professionals (to whose ranks I perhaps can never aspire) will instead work from some such multi-volume reference as L.Köhler, W. Baumartner and J. Stamm, The Hebrew and Aramaic Lexicon of the Old Testament, (translated and edited by M.E.J.Richardson; as of the year 2001, the Richardson version of Köhler-Bamgartner-Stamm is available for a gut-wrenching 300 USD or 400 USD or so, in an unabridged, and yet specially compact, two-volume "study edition" from Boston publisher Brill; the earlier, half-dozen-volume, publication of this lexicon was still more expensive). 





Toomas Karmo: Part G: Perception, Action, and "Subjectivity"

Quality assessment:



On the 5-point scale current in Estonia, and surely in nearby nations, and familiar to observers of the academic arrangements of the late, unlamented, Union of Soviet Socialist Republics (applying the easy and lax standards Kmo deploys in his grubby imaginary "Aleksandr Stepanovitsh Popovi nimeline sangarliku raadio instituut" (the "Alexandr Stepanovitch Popov Institute of Heroic Radio") and his  grubby imaginary "Nikolai Ivanovitsh Lobatshevski nimeline sotsalitsliku matemaatika instituut" (the "Nicolai Ivanovich Lobachevsky Institute of Socialist Mathematics") - where, on the lax and easy grading philosophy of the twin Institutes, 1/5 is "epic fail", 2/5 is "failure not so disastrous as to be epic", 3/5 is "mediocre pass", 4/5 is "good", and 5/5 is "excellent"): 4/5. Justification: There was enough time to write out the  necessary points to reasonable length.


Revision history:


All times in these blog "revision histories" are stated in UTC (Universal Coordinated Time/ Temps Universel Coordoné,  a precisification of the old GMT, or "Greenwich Mean Time"), in the ISO-prescribed YYYYMMDDThhmmZ timestamping format. UTC currently leads Toronto civil time by 4 hours and currently lags Tallinn civil time by 3 hours.

  •  20170717T2059Z/version 2.1.0: Kmo noticed to his surprise, a week or so late in his revision process, an unfortunate slip: he had written rather obscurely "electrochemical disturbance Q, available in principle (not indeed to Kepler but) to the neurophysiology laboratories of the early 20th century", where what was for clarity required was  "electrochemical disturbance Q in the optic nerve, available in principle (not indeed to Kepler but) to the neurophysiology laboratories of the early 20th century".  Having made this small-and-yet-substantive revision, Kmo reserved the right to upload nonsubstantive, purely cosmetic, tweaks over the coming 48 hours, as here-undocumented versions 2.1.1, 2.1.2, 2.1.3, ... .
  • 20170711T0156Z/version 2.0.0: Kmo finished converting his outline into coherent full-sentences prose. He now started a process of polishing. He reserved the right to upload nonsubstantive, purely cosmetic, tweaks over the coming 48 hours, as here-undocumented versions 2.0.1, 2.0.2, 2.0.3, .. . 
  • 20170711T0003Z/version 1.0.0: Kmo uploaded a moderately polished point-form outline. He hoped over the coming 2 hours to convert this into coherent full-sentences prose.

[CAUTION: A bug in the blogger server-side software has in some past weeks shown a propensity to insert inappropriate whitespace at some points in some of my posted essays. If a screen seems to end in empty space, keep scrolling down. The end of the posting is not reached until the usual blogger "Posted by Toomas (Tom) Karmo at" appears. - The blogger software has also shown a propensity to generate HTML that gets formatted in different ways on different client-side browsers, perhaps with some browsers not correctly reading in the entirety of the "Cascading Style Sheets"  (CSS) which on all ordinary Web servers control the browser placement of margins, sidebars, and the like. If you suspect CSS problems in your particular browser, be patient: it is probable that while some content has been shoved into some odd place (for instance, down to the bottom of your browser, where it ought to appear in the right-hand margin), all the server content has been pushed down into your browser in some place or other. - Finally, there may be blogger vagaries, outside my control, in font sizing or interlinear spacing. - Anyone inclined to help with trouble-shooting, or to offer other kinds of technical advice, is welcome to write me via Toomas.Karmo@gmail.com.]


In the last few installments of this multi-part essay, I have tried to articulate, as well as I can, my underlying assumptions (1)  regarding causing (regarding "making-happen") and (2) regarding Other Minds (regarding the existence of "an awareness which is not my own awareness"). 

It is now time to summarize that exposition of underlying assumptions: 

  • For good or ill (for better or worse), I shall here be presupposing a position on causation at variance with an actual, long-dead, rightly respected Scottish authority, to whom we may here refer -  I introduced the reference in "Part C", from 2017-05-29 or 2017-05-30  - as "Darren Gloom" or "Dagwood Spume" or "DEFGH". 
  • For good or ill (for better or worse) I shall here be presupposing a position on Other Minds at variance with an imaginary analogue of DEFGH, the imaginary analyst "Havid Dume", or "HGFED". - Well, in fact "Havid Dume", although imaginary, does have some affinities (as I pointed out in "Part C") with the actual intellectual world. One dimly recalls, from one's reading in that world, the "Curing Test", or the "Luring Test", or something - proposed by some distinguished mathematical logician, soon after the Hitler war. 
Spelling out my divergence from the imagined HGFED proved troublesome. I found in the event that I needed more than just one week's worth of blogging, in my fumbling attempt to take care of a worrisome Philosophy-of-Other-Minds point involving counterfactual conditionals. To summarize that long story: I think that when confronted with radically intelligent, even counterfactually intelligent, verbal behaviour - behaviour that would, counterfactually, even continue seeming intelligent were we, counterfactually, to have administered conversational probes other than the ones we did in fact administer - it remains an open question whether our interlocutor is or is not a possessor of awareness. Are the so-eloquent verbal and facial gyrations, actual and counterfactual, of that fellow member of Homo sapiens (or, again, of that MIT vinyl-and-silicon assemblage) the expressions of a mind other than my own? Or is the so-eloquent fellow human a mere somnanbulist, and the so-eloquent robot a mere unthinking gearbox? It seems to me that the question is open in the sense that both an affirmative and a negative answer are logically coherent. The question seems to me just as much open as the question whether the cosmos is a mere two seconds old, and again just as open as the question whether the parlour furniture continues to exist when not inspected.

I do not say in any of this that the two competing answers in the case of the past, or the two competing answers in the case of the furniture, are equally reasonable. I say only that the question is open in that both competing answers make sense. Neither of them seems incoherent, in the sense in which the notion of a four-sided triangle, or of a married bachelor, is incoherent.

I do realize (here I recapitulate from the "Part F" posting of 2017-06-26 or 2017-06-27) that more needs to be said on DEFGH and HGFED. In particular, I do concede that in arguing, as I have argued over past weeks, that the common speech of humanity embodies reality-of-Causation and reality-of-Other-Minds views at variance with the reductionist DEFGH and the reductionist HGFED, I am dodging deep questions. The deep questions are these: is humanity entitled to embody my two favoured forms of "Realism" in its linguistic practices? I finished my most recent posting in this series (the just-mentioned "Part F") by formally declaring the inadequacy of my (painfully provisional) work, formally raising a "superficiality flag".

****

Having finished exhibiting my underlying assumptions (and having therein, I reiterate, raised my humiliating Flag), I can now at long last return to the main thread of the discussion - following now, with moderate closeness, the outline I published in "Part B", back on 2017-05-22 or 2017-05-23, under the subheading "2. General Project Preview, Through Three Quick-and-Sloppy Fragments".

It is helpful tonight to reproduce, verbatim, the beginning that I made in "Part C" (from 2017-05-29 or 2017-05-30) in converting the outline into a formal exposition:

/.../ Imagine that when walking in town one day, you feel a throbbing pain when you are at the intersection of First Avenue and A Street. Imagine further that as you proceed up First Avenue, the throbbing pain subsides, only to be replaced by a steady nausea when you reach First Avenue and B Street - with this nausea itself subsiding as you leave the intersection behind, on your way up First Avenue to C Street.  Imagine, further, that everyone with whom you discuss the topography of First Avenue reports a pain and a nausea similar to yours, localized to that same pair of intersections.

Maybe everyone's reports are consilient as a matter of sheer coincidence - as when fifty tossed dimes all, astonishingly, land heads-up. (Person A, as it were, had an attack of indigestion from bad pickles upon approaching First and B, and Person B coincidentally had an attack of indigestion at this same intersection from a bout of flu, and so on.) But it would be reasonable to suspect that, far from coincidences being in play, there is something at that pair of intersections which is making everyone feel pain in the one place and nausea at the other. If (if, I stress) the suspicion of common causes is true, then it would be a reasonable use of language to say, "There is a throbbing Pain at the intersection of First Avenue and A Street, and a steady Sick at the intersection of First Avenue and B Street." Although such a use of language would depart from English idiom, it would be coherent: i.e., would possess a well-grasped meaning.

Later on, inquiries could be mounted, to determine what the Pain and the Sick are. Two broad kinds of outcome are possible.

(I) The inquiries may have an outcome favourable from the standpoint of existing natural science. It might turn out that, e.g., everyone is made to be in pain by some concealed loudspeakers, vibrating powerfully at some subsonic frequencies cunningly selected for resonance with the bones of the
Homo sapiens  middle ear, and that the nausea  is induced in everyone by the same colourless gas, venting from some cunningly concealed nozzle. In that case, people would say, "Well, the Pain is a subsonic atmospheric vibration, and the Sick is a gas possessing such-and-such a molecular formula."

(II) The inquiries may lead to no outcome favourable from the standpoint of existing natural science. In that case, people will be like astrophysicists grappling with Dark Matter and Dark Energy: they will aver that there are some easily human-perceptible things on First Avenue (assemblages of non-baryonic matter, perhaps?) whose nature is as yet mysterious. 

Two possible sub-cases now present themselves.

(II.a) Perhaps the Pain and the Sick will prove frustratingly thin in their phenomenology - never moving around, for instance, and never in other ways changing, and so not lending themselves to any very pleasing mathematics.

(II.b) Perhaps, on the other hand, close observation will disclose a more or less rich phenomenology - with the Pain, perhaps, migrating up First Avenue at certain times of the month, and upon reaching B Street either passing unimpeded through the Sick or else pushing the Sick along with it. - In this "II.b" sub-case, people will be able to write out "laws" regarding the behaviour of the Sick and the Pain, and these "laws" might ultimately prove to be just as detailed, and just as amenable to exact mathematical formulation, as the laws governing the movements of electrons and protons in electric and magnetic fields. With laws to hand, it will eventually be suggested that the Sick and the Pain are as well understood as the electron and proton themselves, even while in a sense belonging, perhaps, "to a different Kingdom of Matter, with which ordinary baryonic matter has few points of contact outside the physiology of
Homo sapiens observers". 

Tonight I have to carry on from where I left off, with the "Part C" passage just quoted. 

****

Whichever of the various possibilities "I", "II.a", or "II.b" obtains, people will in any case admit the likelihood that there is something out there on First Avenue - something which is "likely making people be (causing people to be) in pain and sick". (They will, in making this admission, be using the language of "making" and "causing" in a sense I have urged in opposition to the reductionist-minded DEFGH.) 

Tonight I note that the imagined situation with First Avenue differs at most in degree, and not in kind, from humanity's real-world sensory dealings. You sit, Gentle Reader, outdoors, momentarily lifting your gaze from laptop computer to (let us suppose) a sunlit lawn. In the imagined First Avenue scenario, people undergo one kind of thing at the intersection of First Avenue and A Street, and a different kind of thing at the intersection of First Avenue and B Street. For what they undergo at the former intersection, there is a ready idiom, in English and Estonian alike: "We are hurting"/"Me valutame." For what they undergo at the latter intersection, there is no ready idiom, whether in English or in Estonian. French fares a little better - "J'ai mal ici" - "I am sicking here," or literally "I have-sick here" (by analogy with "J'ai soif"/"I am thirsting", or literally "I have-thirst"; "J'ai faim"/"I am hungering", or literally "I have-hunger" - as also with the German "Ich habe Hunger"). 

But these are superficial points of idiom. It would be easy enough to neologize, saying "Everyone who walks through First Avenue and B Street starts sicking."

Consider now the experience of gazing upon sunlit lawn. With the eyes open, and with the afternoon light good, one is undergoing something, for which it is again appropriate to neologize: one is "greening". Such language would indeed become natural and commonplace if we became habitual visitors to neurophysiology labs. As the technicians gradually dial up the voltage applied to electrodes in our cranial cortex, they could appropriately ask us not "Are you hurting now?" but "Are you greening now?" (One possible answer: "Yes, now I am starting to green, just a little, amid all my greying, as when I am out on the lawn under the last light of an evening sky - and now I am greening pretty strongly, almost as strongly as I green when I am out on the lawn in mid-afternoon.") 

I dimly recall some eminent Oxford Catholic philosopher from the 1950s onward, with some such name as Prof. Elizabeth Honeycombe, writing in an illuminating way on action and intention. I seem to recall others - in the USA, a Prof. Arthur C. Dante, or Prof. Arthur C. Dango, or something of the kind - developing related ideas.

"Prof. Honeycombe" and "Prof. Dango" and others, at least as I recall them, used to point out that one thing can get done "in" doing another. An example: in moving one's hand, one can be moving one's pen; and in moving one's pen, one can be signing one's name. A second example: in moving one's hand, one can be transferring a little wooden horse from one region on a chequered wooden panel to a different region; and in moving the little wooden horse, one can be putting a King into checkmate.

I presume the formal structure of doing-in has been explored by "Prof. Honeycombe", or by "Prof. Dango", or by related writers. Without bothering to ponder this carefully tonight, I merely put on record my own impression that doing-in is transitive. If, e.g., one is moving a little wooden horse in moving one's hand, and is putting a King into checkmate in moving the little wooden horse, then one is putting a King into checkmate in moving one's hand.

Whether doing-in is or is not symmetrical, I am not at this instant sure. But I am inclined to write "not symmetrical" - and even more boldly, to write "asymmetrical". If, e.g., one is signing a lease in moving one's pen, then I think it does not follow that one is moving one's pen in signing a lease. And I think it even follows (here we move from mere failure-of-symmetry to outright success-of-asymmetry) that one is not moving one's pen in signing a lease.

Fortunately, so far as I can see tonight, nothing in my work here, as tentatively planned for all the upcoming weeks, is going to require me to explore this formal question of asymmetry, or the further formal question of "connectedness" - to take a stance, in other words, either for or against the proposition that for all x, A, V, and W, if x is V-ing in A-ing, and is W-ing in A-ing, then either x is V-ing in W-ing or x is W-ing in V-ing.

As for "Prof. Honeycombe" and "Prof. Dango" and other such authorities on action, so too, I note tonight, for the philosophy of perception. (Has someone, somewhere, since I left the Departments of Philosophy in 1991, actually developed the "Honeycombe"/"Dango" philosophy-of-action ideas in the direction of perception? If so, then perhaps some kind reader could send me an e-mail, telling me what publications to read? As always, the appropriate address is Toomas.Karmo@gmail.com.) In greening, you, the Gentle Reader currently sitting by your lawn, are seeing sunlit grass. Further, in seeing sunlit grass, you are seeing a garden (of which the lawn is one part), and are seeing a neighbourhood (of which the garden is one part).

****

I next note that this chain of seeing-in has not only the evident outward links just mentioned, but also links of a more recondite kind - not evident to common sense, and yet evident enough to anatomists. Not only is it the case that in greening you are seeing the lawn: it is also the case that in greening you are seeing a small patch of greenish light on the surface of a Homo sapiens retina. It is a patch of light at most a few millimetres across. Its upper edge (the part closes to your hairline) corresponds to that part of the lawn which is closest to your chair. Its lower edge (the part closest to your teeth) corresponds to that part of the lawn which is farthest from your chair. (The correspondence has this rather awkward inverting twist because, rather awkwardly, the patch of light is formed by a convex, and therefore inverting, crystalline lens, just inside your cornea.) So a fuller description of the perceptual situation is the following: In greening, you see a patch of light on a Homo sapiens retina; and in seeing that patch of light, you see the lawn; and in seeing the lawn, you see the garden; and in seeing the garden, you see the neighbourhood. 

If the "patch of light" link in this asserted chain seems odd, it is helpful to recall that we can on any adequate account of perception be on occasion seeing something without realizing what it is we see. The prosecuting barrister asks you, as you stand in the witness box at the Old Bailey, "Did you see Prof. Plum in the conservatory, on the night Colonel Mustard was found dead beside that lead pipe which you have just affirmed for the Court to be Exhibit Q?" A properly careful answer to this will be something like the following: Well, I did, although I did not realize it at the time. I saw a flash of something purple, and I thought it might have been one of the observatory peacocks. But an hour later, when guests came down to dinner, I realized that what I had glimpsed in the conservatory was likely to have been Prof. Plum. For at dinner Prof. Plum was in his loudly iridescent purple blazer, which I believe to be the item entered by the Crown as Exhibit R in this Court [and so on, and so on].

(There is a tight parallel here with the formalities of action. It is possible to be (a) Y-ing in X-ing, and aware that one is X-ing without being aware that one is Y-ing, and (b) to be Y-ing in X-ing, and aware that one is Y-ing without being aware that one is X-ing. One might be, in practicing the bagpipes, traumatizing the neighbours. It is easy to do the former without realizing that one is doing the latter. Conversely, one might, in closing Relay 17 behind the motorcar dashboard, be signalling a left turn - aware enough that one is doing the latter, and yet (being untrained in motor mechanics) unaware that one is doing the former.)

The seen patch of green light is in no sense a "sense datum" or "sense impression", being fully public. It can in principle be inspected with an ophthalmoscope. That it is in seeing it that the lawn is seen is a fact which, while not obvious, was nevertheless already available in principle to the Renaissance anatomists (and, I gather from  https://web.stanford.edu/class/history13/earlysciencelab/body/eyespages/eye.html, was grasped by, or was on the verge of being grasped by, Renaissance astronomer Johannes Kepler).

In moving from lawn to retinal surface, we are moving inward in the Homo sapiens body. This exploration can be taken a little farther. Not only is the lawn seen in seeing the green patch; the green patch is itself seen in seeing some electrochemical disturbance Q in the optic nerve, available in principle (not indeed to Kepler but) to the neurophysiology laboratories of the early 20th century. Finally, Q itself is seen in seeing something P, for all I know a thing not yet fully mapped by the anatomists - a pattern of electrochemical activity not proceeding along the optic nerve, but instead occurring deeper within the human body, in the visual cortex.

In all of this, I note, the fact that we can be blissfully unaware of seeing the patch of retinal light - or unaware of seeing it in seeing Q, or unaware of seeing Q in seeing P - is no different in principle from the banal courtroom witness-stand fact that we can be seeing Prof. Plum without being aware of seeing him.

****

I now come to a fundamental thesis, which I shall have to defend in the next installment of this essay, one or two or three or so weeks from tonight: there is no sense in which the greening either "matches" or "mismatches" the grass.

Suppose that, having resolved to improve your lifestyle, you embark on the celebrated Paleolithic Diet. No sooner have you begun the Diet, so rich in nuts and meats, than your colour vision is disturbed. Grass suddenly assumes for you the colour aspect of tomato ketchup, and ketchup the aspect of grass (and so on for all other red and green things - the world seems to you to flip in the way a colour-television scene would flip if a technician were to interchange the R and G links between video amplifier and display screen). As you discontinue the Diet, your vision snaps back to its previous condition. As you resume the Diet, the disturbance recurs.

What has happened? Was your colour vision accurate when you were not on the Diet, only to be perturbed when you went Paleolithic? Or was it, rather, the case that your colour vision had been systematically distorted by the malign industrial foods on ordinary grocery shelves - the salt, the sugar, the wheat, the beans - to be rendered veracious by the austere régime of our virtuous Paleolithic ancestors? ("Wretches!" proclaims a Pythagorean fragment, in what I picture as an authentically Paleolithic, Google-searchable diet-fad, spirit: "Utter wretches! Keep your hands from beans!")

I leave it to the reader to anticipate, as relatively easy homework, how I shall have to develop this theme in the next installment. (I shall have to draw parallels with Einsteinean, or indeed with Galilean-Newtonian, mechanics, in which "All motion is frame-relative", and "There is no one privileged inertial frame of reference": how will these parallels go?)

As a further, less easy, piece of homework, the reader can consider whether the point I have just started developing for colour vision possesses parallels, or on the contrary lacks parallels, in a more basic aspect of human sensory functioning - in the visual perception of mere shapes, and of mere right-left, up-down, orientations. Some in Departments of Philosophy affirm, following John Locke (1632-1704), that there is a deep logical difference between perception of colour and perception of shape and orientation. Others in Departments of Philosophy deny this. Who is right - those who affirm, or those who deny?

[This is the end of the present blog posting. It is hoped that the next installment, "Part H", of the multi-part perception-and-action essay will be uploaded one or two or three or so weeks from today.]